Difference between revisions of "Tenses of English"

From Glottopedia
Jump to navigation Jump to search
 
(8 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
== What is a Tense?  ==
 
== What is a Tense?  ==
  
As pointed out by Klein (1995: 141), 2500 years of research have not led to any precise or universally acknowledged definition of the category 'tense'. However, there is a widespread understanding of what 'tense' basically means. Such an 'understood' definition is for instance given in the International Encyclopedia of Linguistics (Bybee 1992: 223f.):
+
As pointed out by Klein (1995: 141), 2500 years of research have not led to any precise or universally acknowledged definition of the category '[[tense]]', there is a widespread understanding of what 'tense' basically means. Such an 'understood' definition is for instance given in the ''International Encyclopedia of Linguistics'' (Bybee 1992: 223f.):
  
 
Tense refers to the grammatical expression of the time of the situation described in the proposition, relative to some other time. This other time may be the moment of speech, e. g. the past and future designate time before and after the moment of speech, respectively [...]. Tense is expressed by inflections, by particles, or by auxiliaries in construction with the verb [...].
 
Tense refers to the grammatical expression of the time of the situation described in the proposition, relative to some other time. This other time may be the moment of speech, e. g. the past and future designate time before and after the moment of speech, respectively [...]. Tense is expressed by inflections, by particles, or by auxiliaries in construction with the verb [...].
Line 11: Line 11:
 
=== Two Tense Approach ===
 
=== Two Tense Approach ===
  
Linguists who favor a binary approach argue that different tenses have to be distinguished morphologically, that is they have to be reflected in inflectional morphology. Accordingly, there are only two tenses, namely ‘past’ and ‘non-past’, as this is the only distinction that is reflected morphologically.
+
Linguists who favor a binary approach argue that different tenses have to be distinguished morphologically, that is they have to be reflected in inflectional [[morphology]]. Accordingly, there are only two tenses, namely ‘past’ and ‘non-past’, as this is the only distinction that is reflected morphologically.
  
 
(1) He work - s.
 
(1) He work - s.
Line 27: Line 27:
 
*future II,
 
*future II,
  
which might rather be used by linguists who recognize these as 'basic' tenses,.
+
which might rather be used by linguists who recognize these as 'basic' tenses.
 
The binary approach is found in “many structuralist accounts” (König 1995: 154) such as the comprehensive grammar by Quirk et al. (1985).
 
The binary approach is found in “many structuralist accounts” (König 1995: 154) such as the comprehensive grammar by Quirk et al. (1985).
  
 
=== Three Tense Approach ===
 
=== Three Tense Approach ===
 
Some linguists have argued against regarding a sentence like ''We will/'ll miss the train'' as a combination of the present + the verb ''will'' + the infinitive ''miss''. König (1995: 154) considers such an interpretation “untenable and synchronically inadequate”, as ''will'' has lost both morphological substance (it may be reduced to '''ll'') and semantic substance (since it no longer solely expresses volition, is no longer restricted to human beings and combines freely with the progressive and have).
 
Some linguists have argued against regarding a sentence like ''We will/'ll miss the train'' as a combination of the present + the verb ''will'' + the infinitive ''miss''. König (1995: 154) considers such an interpretation “untenable and synchronically inadequate”, as ''will'' has lost both morphological substance (it may be reduced to '''ll'') and semantic substance (since it no longer solely expresses volition, is no longer restricted to human beings and combines freely with the progressive and have).
These developments allow for the interpretation of ''will'' as a future tense marker. ''Will'' has undergone a process of grammaticalization, during which a new grammatical category has developed. This view of the existence of three tenses (present, past, future) can be found in Klein (1994) and Hatav (1993), among other authors.
+
These developments allow for the interpretation of ''will'' as a future tense marker. ''Will'' has undergone a process of [[grammaticalization]], during which a new grammatical category has developed. This view of the existence of three tenses (present, past, future) can be found in Klein (1994) and Hatav (1993), among other authors.
  
 
=== Six Tense Approach ===
 
=== Six Tense Approach ===
Line 83: Line 83:
  
 
=== Temporal Relations – Absolute and Relative Tenses ===
 
=== Temporal Relations – Absolute and Relative Tenses ===
Declerck differentiates between absolute and relative tenses. Absolute tenses are those which express “a direct temporal relation with the temporal zero-point (= t<sub>0</sub>)” (Declerck 2006: 25), just as in (6). Relative tenses are those which express “a single temporal relation between the time of the situation referred to and an orientation time other than the zero-time (= t<sub>0</sub>)” (ibid.), just like in (7). Relative tenses express one of the following temporal relations:
+
Declerck differentiates between absolute and relative tenses. [[Absolute tense]]s are those which express “a direct temporal relation with the temporal zero-point (= t<sub>0</sub>)” (Declerck 2006: 25), just as in (6). [[Relative tense]]s are those which express “a single temporal relation between the time of the situation referred to and an orientation time other than the zero-time (= t<sub>0</sub>)” (ibid.), just like in (7). Relative tenses express one of the following temporal relations:
 
*anteriority: the situation time precedes the orientation time: He said he had got up early.
 
*anteriority: the situation time precedes the orientation time: He said he had got up early.
 
*simultaneity: the situation time coincides with the orientation time: He said he didn't feel well.
 
*simultaneity: the situation time coincides with the orientation time: He said he didn't feel well.
Line 92: Line 92:
 
Relative tenses are: past perfect, conditional.
 
Relative tenses are: past perfect, conditional.
  
The future perfect and the conditional perfect express two temporal relations at the same time: “the time of the situation is represented as anterior to an orientation time which is itself represented as posterior to another time” (Declerck 2006: 25). In the case of the future perfect, this 'other time' is t<sub>0</sub>, which makes the future perfect an absolute-relative tense, because it relates its situation time to an orientation time (this is the relative component) which is itself related to t<sub>0</sub> (this is the absolute component). With the conditional perfect, neither of the orientation times is t<sub>0</sub>, which means that this tense has two relative components; Declerck calls this tense a 'complex relative tense' (2006: 25).  
+
The future perfect and the conditional perfect express two temporal relations at the same time: “the time of the situation is represented as anterior to an orientation time which is itself represented as posterior to another time” (Declerck 2006: 25). In the case of the future perfect, this 'other time' is t<sub>0</sub>, which makes the future perfect an [[absolute-relative tense]], because it relates its situation time to an orientation time (this is the relative component) which is itself related to t<sub>0</sub> (this is the absolute component). With the conditional perfect, neither of the orientation times is t<sub>0</sub>, which means that this tense has two relative components; Declerck calls this tense a '[[complex relative tense]]' (2006: 25).  
  
 
=== Tenses ===
 
=== Tenses ===
Line 131: Line 131:
 
(12) I lived in a flat for ten years. (implicates that I don't live in a flat anymore)
 
(12) I lived in a flat for ten years. (implicates that I don't live in a flat anymore)
  
As with other implicatures, this interpretation of the entire situation having ended can be cancelled by the context. Thus, a situation in the past tense can of course still be actualizing at t0:
+
As with other implicatures, this interpretation of the entire situation having ended can be cancelled by the context. Thus, a situation in the past tense can of course still be actualizing at t<sub>0</sub>:
  
 
(13) [“Where is John?” – “I don't know. But look in the kitchen.] He was there two minutes ago. [Perhaps he is still there.”]  
 
(13) [“Where is John?” – “I don't know. But look in the kitchen.] He was there two minutes ago. [Perhaps he is still there.”]  
Line 227: Line 227:
  
 
== Literature ==
 
== Literature ==
Declerck, Renaat (1991). ''Tense in English: Its Structure and Use in Discourse.'' London: Routledge.
+
*Declerck, Renaat (1991). ''Tense in English: Its Structure and Use in Discourse.'' London: Routledge.
 +
*Declerck, Renaat (2006). ''The Grammar of the English Tense System: a Comprehensive Analysis.'' Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
 +
*Klein, Wolfgang (1995). A Simplest Analysis of the English Tense-Aspect System. In: Riehle, Wolfgang/Keiper, Hugo (eds.). ''Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1994.'' Tübingen: Niemeyer. 139-151.
 +
*König, Ekkehard (1995). On Analyzing the Tense-Aspect System of English: A State-of-the-Art Report. In: Riehle, Wolfgang/Keiper, Hugo (eds.). ''Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1994.'' Tübingen: Niemeyer. 153–169.
  
Declerck, Renaat (2006). ''The Grammar of the English Tense System: a Comprehensive Analysis.'' Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
 
  
Klein, Wolfgang (1995). A Simplest Analysis of the English Tense-Aspect System. In: Riehle, Wolfgang/Keiper, Hugo (eds.). ''Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1994.'' Tübingen: Niemeyer. 139-151.
+
[[Category:En]]
 
+
[[Category:DICT]]
König, Ekkehard (1995). On Analyzing the Tense-Aspect System of English: A State-of-the-Art Report. In: Riehle, Wolfgang/Keiper, Hugo (eds.). ''Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1994.'' Tübingen: Niemeyer. 153–169.
+
[[Category:Morphology]]

Latest revision as of 16:34, 27 July 2014

What is a Tense?

As pointed out by Klein (1995: 141), 2500 years of research have not led to any precise or universally acknowledged definition of the category 'tense', there is a widespread understanding of what 'tense' basically means. Such an 'understood' definition is for instance given in the International Encyclopedia of Linguistics (Bybee 1992: 223f.):

Tense refers to the grammatical expression of the time of the situation described in the proposition, relative to some other time. This other time may be the moment of speech, e. g. the past and future designate time before and after the moment of speech, respectively [...]. Tense is expressed by inflections, by particles, or by auxiliaries in construction with the verb [...].

Different Approaches

How many tenses are there in English? This is a simple question, to which, however, almost every linguist gives a different answer. According to Bublitz (1995: 135), these “dissenting views are reflected by the fact that linguists have yet to agree on the number of tenses [...] in English, which vary according to whether formal or semantic criteria or a combination of both are recognized. In particular, the present perfect, the past perfect and the future perfect defy easy categorization.” Linguists' different views on the number of English tenses can be grouped into four different approaches (cf. König 1995).

Two Tense Approach

Linguists who favor a binary approach argue that different tenses have to be distinguished morphologically, that is they have to be reflected in inflectional morphology. Accordingly, there are only two tenses, namely ‘past’ and ‘non-past’, as this is the only distinction that is reflected morphologically.

(1) He work - s.

(2) He work - ed.

All other categories of the English tense system are constituted by a combination of one of the two above-mentioned tenses with either a modal verb, or the perfect marker have. The advocates of this approach often conveniently stress the “combinatorial character” (König 1995: 154) of these members by naming them

  • present perfect
  • past perfect
  • future perfect

rather than

  • perfect
  • pluperfect
  • future II,

which might rather be used by linguists who recognize these as 'basic' tenses. The binary approach is found in “many structuralist accounts” (König 1995: 154) such as the comprehensive grammar by Quirk et al. (1985).

Three Tense Approach

Some linguists have argued against regarding a sentence like We will/'ll miss the train as a combination of the present + the verb will + the infinitive miss. König (1995: 154) considers such an interpretation “untenable and synchronically inadequate”, as will has lost both morphological substance (it may be reduced to 'll) and semantic substance (since it no longer solely expresses volition, is no longer restricted to human beings and combines freely with the progressive and have). These developments allow for the interpretation of will as a future tense marker. Will has undergone a process of grammaticalization, during which a new grammatical category has developed. This view of the existence of three tenses (present, past, future) can be found in Klein (1994) and Hatav (1993), among other authors.

Six Tense Approach

In those approaches where six English tenses are distinguished, the list of tenses in most cases includes the following (cf. König 1995: 155):

  • present
  • past
  • future tense
  • present perfect (= perfect)
  • past perfect (= pluperfect)
  • future perfect (= future II)

This model is often based on the model of Latin grammar and on the assumption that combinatorial tenses such as the last three are only apparently compositional, i.e. from a morphological point of view, while being largely non-compositional semantically (“the combinatorial formal make-up of present perfect, past perfect, future perfect has no parallel in a compositional derivation of their meaning”, König 1995: 155).

The more-than-two tense approach is reflected in simple terms such as perfect and pluperfect (cf. Comrie 1985).

Eight Tense Approach

In addition to the six tenses mentioned above, Declerck (1990) includes two more tenses: the conditional tense and the conditional perfect. Declerck argues against a compositional analysis of combinatorial tenses. Aiming to account for the use of tenses in narrative discourse, he assumes two further tenses which, in his view, cannot be subsumed under any other category:

(3) At 5 o'clock, he would have left the hotel.

Historical Development

The evolution of a future and perfect tense (as acknowledged by some linguists) represents the most significant innovation of Modern English in comparison to earlier stages of that language. Old English had a two tense system (past and non-past; cf. Section 2.1), which is claimed to have been preserved in Modern English by some linguists. Crosslinguistic work (Bybee/Dahl 1989) has shown that future tense markers typically derive from:

  • verbs of volition
  • verbs of obligation
  • verbs of motion

During a process of grammaticalization such verbs lose specific aspects of their meaning, and thus also broadening their distribution (e. g. to human beings) and/or morphological properties:

(4) It is going to rain.

(5) It's gonna rain.

Words may, in the process of grammaticalization, also acquire semantic substance. In the development of future tense markers it is the element of prediction and intention that is newly acquired. In specific contexts (e. g. future time reference), the choice of lexical or grammatical future tense marking is obligatory (e. g. will and going to), lending support to the view that the grammaticalization in this area is advanced. The expression that has advanced furthest as a future tense marker in English is will, as it combines freely with any type of verb and aspect.

The perfect is another example of the latest developments of the English tense system. Comparative linguists have identified typical historical sources of perfect markers, such as the verb have and the adverb already (König 1995: 164). The English perfect has developed from originally resultative sentences with be (John is gone) and have (I have the enemy bound). Such resultative sentences express states and/or possession over states. The change from resultative meaning to perfect meaning comes about due to a semantic change “as a result of which the responsibility for the action leading to the state is ascribed to the subject” (König 1995: 164). In other languages (though not in English), the perfect is also used as a narrative tense, thus gradually replacing (and presumably eventually eliminating) the past tense (preterite).

Declerck's Theory of Tense

This section provides a brief description of the temporal system proposed by Declerck (1991, 2006). For the sake of comprehensibility, Declerck's terminology and basic assumptions will be briefly outlined.

Terminology

Declerck (2006: 22) conceives of tense as a “linguistic concept [which] denotes the form taken by the verb to [...] express the temporal relation between the time of the situation in question and an 'orientation time' which may be either the 'temporal zero-point' (which is usually the time of speech [...]) or another orientation time that is temporally related to the temporal zero-point.” The orientation time is “[a]ny time that can provide the 'known' time (or one of the known times) required for the expression of the temporal relation(s) encoded in a tense form” (Declerck 2006: 117). The temporal zero-point (t0) is the point in time from which all expressed temporal relations take their starting point. It is usually (but not necessarily) the time of the utterance.

In (6) below, the orientation time corresponds to t0, whereas in (7), the past tense form confessed locates the time of the confession in the past, and the past perfect form had stolen expresses that the situation (namely the theft) was committed even before the confession. In the latter case, the time of the confession is thus the orientation time for the past perfect form, which in turn lies before (and therefore does not equal) t0. The form had stolen locates the situation relative to an orientation time which is itself located relative to speech time (=t0).

(6) I met him last night.

(7) Last night he confessed that he had stolen the money.

Temporal Relations – Absolute and Relative Tenses

Declerck differentiates between absolute and relative tenses. Absolute tenses are those which express “a direct temporal relation with the temporal zero-point (= t0)” (Declerck 2006: 25), just as in (6). Relative tenses are those which express “a single temporal relation between the time of the situation referred to and an orientation time other than the zero-time (= t0)” (ibid.), just like in (7). Relative tenses express one of the following temporal relations:

  • anteriority: the situation time precedes the orientation time: He said he had got up early.
  • simultaneity: the situation time coincides with the orientation time: He said he didn't feel well.
  • posteriority: the situation time follows the orientation time: He said he would save us.

Absolute tenses are: present, past, present perfect, future.

Relative tenses are: past perfect, conditional.

The future perfect and the conditional perfect express two temporal relations at the same time: “the time of the situation is represented as anterior to an orientation time which is itself represented as posterior to another time” (Declerck 2006: 25). In the case of the future perfect, this 'other time' is t0, which makes the future perfect an absolute-relative tense, because it relates its situation time to an orientation time (this is the relative component) which is itself related to t0 (this is the absolute component). With the conditional perfect, neither of the orientation times is t0, which means that this tense has two relative components; Declerck calls this tense a 'complex relative tense' (2006: 25).

Tenses

The only two tenses which can be differentiated morphologically are the present and the past. All other tenses are formed with the help of auxiliaries. These other tenses are called 'complex tenses', where the first auxiliary (= the operator, i.e. either have or will) is morphologically in the present or past tense (cf. Declerck 2006: 24).

All tenses which show present tense inflection (present perfect, future, future perfect) create a present time-sphere. All tenses exhibiting past tense morphology (past perfect, conditional tense, conditional perfect) create a past time-sphere (cf. Declerck 2006: 156). Declerck specifies the concept of ‘time-sphere’ as follows: English tenses “reflect a mental division of time into past and nonpast. The main evidence for this is that all tenses carry either a past or a nonpast (present) tense morpheme. There is no future tense morpheme” (2006: 147). Declerck represents this mental division of time as two time-spheres (cf. above), in which the different tenses are situated.

The present time-sphere contains the present zone (which coincides with t0), the pre-present zone (which leads up to t0), and the post-present zone (which begins immediately after t0). In order to locate a situation in one of these zones, the present, present perfect or future are used.

The past time-sphere lies wholly before t0. In order to locate a situation in the past time-sphere, the past perfect, conditional tense or conditional perfect are used. The past time-sphere is conceived of as disconnected from the present time-sphere.

Present

The forms of the present of all verbs (except be and have) are homophonous with the stem of the verb (e. g. forget), except in the third person singular (e. g. forgets). The meaning of the present tense is that “the situation time (i. e. the time of the predicted situation) coincides with t0” (Declerck 2006: 173). Since t0 is a point in time, the situation time is also a point in time. The full situation expressed by the tense form takes one of the following forms:

(i) One possibility is that the entire situation is punctual. In this case the situation time coincides with the time of the entire situation and is thus punctual, too.

(8) [Now watch closely.] I hit the nail once with a hammer.

(ii) Another possibility is that the entire situation is durative. In this case, the situation time cannot be located at (punctual) t0. Thus, if the entire situation is durative, the situation time “can be a punctual subinterval of the time of the full situation and that punctual subinterval can be located at t0” (Declerck 2006: 173). This is only possible if the entire situation is homogeneous, which means that the sentence denoting the situation can be used not only to describe the situation as a whole, but also each portion of it (e. g. in the durative process of working, each 'subpart' of working is also working).

(9) I am working.

Sentence (9) is homogeneous: if I am working for a period of time, then this sentence is a valid description of any part of the situation that coincides with t0.

Past

The regular past tense form consists of the stem of the verb and (an allophone of) the suffix -ed (e. g. walked). Verbs which form their past in this way are called 'weak verbs' or 'regular verbs'. There is another large group of English verbs which are called 'strong verbs' or 'irregular verbs'. These verbs form their past not by adding a suffix, but by other means, e. g. vowel gradation ('Ablaut'), change of single letters, or a completely different word (e. g. sink – sank, bend – bent, be – was/were).

The past tense is used to locate a situation time in the past time-sphere. A speaker uses the past when s/he is not thinking of t0 (unlike in the use of the present perfect, cf. Chapter 4.3.3). In other words, s/he is not concerned with NOW, but with THEN, i.e. a specific period in the past which can be either definite or indefinite. The past is used when a speaker is concerned with “the past situation itself, rather than with its possible relation to the present” (Declerck 2006: 195).

In order for sentences in the past to be interpretable, they have to establish a so-called 'anchor-time' (mostly by adverbials), which can be either definite or indefinite. (10) is not fully interpretable in isolation, whereas (11) is fully interpretable since an anchor-time ('Once upon a time') is given.

(10) ?There was a princess who felt very lonely.

(11) Once upon a time there was a princess who felt very lonely.

If the entire situation is durative and homogeneous, and if there is no indication that the situation time is not the time of the entire situation, the past tense normally implicates that the entire situation is completely over at t0. This implicature is founded on the assumption that, since statements about the present are more relevant than statements about the past or future, a situation that includes t0 should be located in the present, not in the past. Hence, if a speaker uses the past tense, this is interpreted as a sign that the speaker cannot use the present tense because the situation is completely over:

(12) I lived in a flat for ten years. (implicates that I don't live in a flat anymore)

As with other implicatures, this interpretation of the entire situation having ended can be cancelled by the context. Thus, a situation in the past tense can of course still be actualizing at t0:

(13) [“Where is John?” – “I don't know. But look in the kitchen.] He was there two minutes ago. [Perhaps he is still there.”]

When uttering He was there two minutes ago the speaker focuses on that part of the situation which is simultaneous with the anchor-time indicated by two minutes ago. However, s/he does not make any claim about other parts of the entire situation. In this case, the situation time is represented as past, but this does not exclude the possibility of the full situation still actualizing at t0.

Present Perfect

The present perfect is an English tense which locates a situation time in the pre-present time zone of the present time-sphere leading up to, but not necessarily including, t0. It is a complex tense, composed by a form of to have and the past participle of a main verb.

(14) I have waited.

Unlike the past tense, a speaker uses the present perfect when s/he wishes to refer not to a definite moment of occurrence of the event, but either simply to the anteriority of the event, or to an event in the past that is considered to be still relevant NOW (in t0):

(15) They have left for Hawaii. They left for Hawaii an hour ago.

If a clause contains an adverbial which specifies the situation time, as in She hasn't seen him for a year, the pre-present zone is taken to be the time denoted by the adverbial (i. e. the interval denoted by the time-specifying adverbial). Declerck differentiates between two possible interpretations of the present perfect: the “before now” interpretation, and the “co-extensive” interpretation. The different interpretations of the present perfect are due to different relations between the situation time and t0. The “before now” interpretation is valid in clauses containing the present perfect in which the situation time lies wholly before t0.

(16) I have already met that girl.

The “co-extensive” interpretation is valid if the situation time is co-extensive with the pre-present and leads up to t0 (with or without including t0).

(17) I've been reading this book.

In both interpretations, the beginning of the pre-present zone can be specified by time adverbials. If there is no adverbial, the pre-present zone is taken to be the shortest possible period up to t0, depending on the semantics of the relevant clause.

Within the scope of this analysis, three temporal readings can be distinguished which further specify the above-mentioned two categories:

  • the 'indefinite' reading: the whole situation comes to an end before t0
  • the 'up-to-now' reading: the whole situation leads up to but ends before t0
  • the 'continuative' reading: the whole situation leads up to and includes t0

Past Perfect

The past perfect is complex tense, made up of a form of to have in the past and the past participle of a main verb.

(18) I had done it.

The past perfect behaves similarly to the past, the main difference being that the past is an absolute tense, while the past perfect is a relative one.

As in the case of the past, a speaker uses the past perfect when s/he wishes to locate a situation time in the past time-sphere, but unlike in the past, this situation time is anterior to an orientation time other than t0 in the past perfect. The relevant clause may receive the interpretation of “situation time completely before orientation time” (Declerck 2006: 445) (similar to the 'indefinite' reading of the present perfect); or the reading “situation time co-extensive with the period leading up to the orientation time” (ibid.) (which would be a past counterpart of the 'up-to-now' reading of the present perfect).

As with the present and the past, the situation time may coincide with the time of the entire situation, or else be a “punctual subinterval” (Declerck 2006: 173) of the full situation (if the entire situation is not punctual; cf. Section 4.3.1).

The past perfect can be used to express the modal concept of counterfactuality in that-clauses depending on the verb wish:

(19) I wish (that) I had never met him.

Future

The English future is a complex tense which can be expressed in one of two ways. It is either composed by the verb will + the infinitive of a main verb (20); or by a form of be going to + the infinitive of the main verb (21):

(20) I will go.

(21) I am going to go.

The future is used when a speaker wants to refer to a situation time that lies in the post-present zone of the present time-sphere. The situation can be located completely after t0 (22), or it can include a timespan which begins at t0 and stretches into the future (23).

(22) I will do it next week.

(23) The term which I will henceforth use to refer to this...

Declerck considers the future with going to an alternative to the future with will, which, in his view, is used “when the speaker wishes to represent the future situation as having its roots in the present” (Declerck 1991: 370).

Typically, the future tense is used as in (22), i.e. to refer to a situation lying wholly after t0. This tense carries an implicature that the situation begins after t0; only when this implicature is cancelled by an adverbial or the general pragmatics of the sentence is the reading 'from t0 onwards' possible (in (23), the implicature would be cancelled by the adverbial henceforth). This implicature is based on the assumption that, since statements about the present are more relevant than statements about the past or future, a situation that starts (and holds) at t0 should not be expressed with a past or future tense, unless there is a valid reason for it (cf. Chapter 4.3.2).

So-called 'futurish forms', which are not ‘genuine’ future forms, are often used to “combine reference to a post-present actualization with a sense of present judgement” (Declerck 2006: 337). Some of these forms could be said to refer to the present rather than to the future. Declerck states that “[t]heir use as a futurish form is a metaphorical extension of this [...]: the post-present is treated as if it were the present” (2006: 337):

(24) I'm leaving. (The situation that is referred to begins either at t0 or in the post-present; if the latter interpretation is the one intended by the speaker, it has to be indicated specifically by contextual cues, as this tense form implicates the former..)

In sentences like Meg {is leaving, is to leave, leaves} tomorrow, a 'futurish' tense form is used. Such forms differ from future tense form in that they make dual time reference. This means that they refer to both present time and future time. The actualization of the situation is in the future; however, there are already indications (e. g. arrangements) in the present for the situation in the future. In the sentence The train leaves at 10 a. m., the situation (the departure of the train) will actualize in the future, but the reference is also to the scheduling of the train's timetable, which exists already at t0.

Future Perfect

The English future perfect is a complex tense which can also be expressed in one of two ways. It is either composed by the verb will in the present tense + the perfect infinitive of a main verb (25); or by a form of be going to in the present tense + the perfect infinitive of the main verb (26).

(25) I will have done it by 5 p.m.

(26) I am going to have done it by 5 p.m.

As pointed out in Section 3.2, the future perfect expresses two temporal relations at the same time: the time of the situation is anterior to an orientation time which itself is posterior to another time (in case of the future perfect, this 'other time' is t0):

The future perfect is thus an absolute-relative tense. It relates its situation time to an orientation time (this is the ‘relative’ component, since these two elements are not temporally fixed). The orientation time, in turn, is related to t0 (this is the absolute component, since t0, being the time of utterance, is temporally fixed). In a sentence like John will have left when we arrive, John's leaving constitutes the situation time, which is anterior to the orientation time (our arriving). The orientation time, in turn, is posterior to t0.

Conditional Tense

The English conditional tense (as defined by Declerck 1990, 2006) is a compound tense which is composed by the verb will in the past tense + the infinitive of a main verb (22).

(27) [I promised that] I would do it.

A speaker uses the conditional tense when s/he refers to a situation time that is posterior to an orientation time which lies in the past time sphere. The use of the conditional tense does not specify whether the situation time is anterior, simultaneous or posterior to t0. Thus, in a sentence like John said he would pray for her it is not clear whether John has already prayed, is doing so right now or will pray in the future.

Conditional Perfect

The English conditional perfect is a compound tense which is formed by combining the verb will in the past tense + the perfect infinitive of a main verb (28).

(28) [I promised that] I would have done it by 5 p.m.

A speaker uses the conditional perfect when s/he refers to a situation time which is anterior to an orientation time, with the latter in turn being posterior to some orientation time in the past time-sphere. In a sentence like Bill promised that he would have finished by the end of the day, the finishing is interpreted as anterior to the end of the day, which in turn is posterior to the time Bill made his promise.

Literature

  • Declerck, Renaat (1991). Tense in English: Its Structure and Use in Discourse. London: Routledge.
  • Declerck, Renaat (2006). The Grammar of the English Tense System: a Comprehensive Analysis. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
  • Klein, Wolfgang (1995). A Simplest Analysis of the English Tense-Aspect System. In: Riehle, Wolfgang/Keiper, Hugo (eds.). Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1994. Tübingen: Niemeyer. 139-151.
  • König, Ekkehard (1995). On Analyzing the Tense-Aspect System of English: A State-of-the-Art Report. In: Riehle, Wolfgang/Keiper, Hugo (eds.). Proceedings of the Anglistentag 1994. Tübingen: Niemeyer. 153–169.